I'm just throwing this out there. Read at your own risk. I don't know what I'm talking about (even more than usual). I'm just thinking out loud, and being ornery. I will explain where I'm coming from after I've made my point.
There's a difference between "strategic complementarity" and "positive externalities". Strategic complementarity is what creates cities. But cities don't necessarily create positive externalities. "Network externalities" is a bit of a BS term that conflates two conceptually distinct things.
Here's a very simple abstract game to illustrate the difference. (I think I stole this from Cooper and John [Update to fix link:JSTOR link Here, Working Paper version link Here.])
All agents are identical. Each agent has a utility function U(x,y), where x is his own action and y is the action chosen by others. In symmetric Nash equilibrium {x*,y*}, where each agent chooses x to maximise his utility taking y as given, and all make the same choice, we know that Ux(x*,y*)=0 and x*=y*. (And Uxx(x*,y*) < 0 for the second order condition).
"Strategic complementarity" means Uxy(x*,y*) > 0. "Positive externality" means Uy(x*,y*) > 0. Those are different things.
Strategic complementarity means if others do something, that increases your marginal utility of doing the same thing. Positive externality means if others do something, that increases your utility. Period.
Here's an example with strategic complementarity and a negative externality:
The blue curves are the representative agent's indifference curves. They are supposed to be sort of oval-shaped, centred around his Personal Bliss point (but I could only draw bits of them). The agent chooses X to maximise his utility, taking other agents' choice Y as given. That means his red Reaction Function will pass through all the points where his indifference curves are vertical. Symmetric Nash equilibrium is where his reaction function crosses the X=Y 45 degree line.
It is easy to see that in this example there is strategic complementarity. The reaction function has a positive slope. If other agents increase their Y, the representative agent increases his X.
It is also easy to see that in this example there is a negative externality, at least in the neighbourhood of the Nash Equilibrium. If other agents increase their Y, that reduces the utility of the representative agent.
What this means is that each individual agent wants to move in the same direction as the others, but they all move too far in that direction. The Symmetric Optimum is where they all back off a bit. But it is not individually rational to back off from the Nash Equilibrium. It's a Prisoners' Dilemma.
Translated into Urban economics, they all crowd into the high density city centre, and it is individually rational for each agent to do so, but all agents would be better off if they were all packed in a bit less densely. There's too much city in equilibrium. At the margin, cities are bad things.
Now, that's just an example, of course. I could have picked a different set of indifference curves where there is strategic complementarity and a positive externality, where cities would be good things (at the margin). But it does illustrate my point: it could go either way.
Google gives me 563,000 hits for "Urban Economics" and 114,000 hits for "Rural Economics". Hmmm. I wonder if that tells us that economists' perspective is urbane, civilised, and maybe just a little bit biased? Rustication is something that university people try to avoid.
Think of this post as a written by someone fresh from the idiocy of rural life, and macroeconomic theory, trying to find his own way around the big city unaided, and very very abstractly. Or think of it as pushback. But there is something very strange, from a general equilibrium perspective, about "Urban economics" as a subject area. It fails the Lake Wobegone test. You can't have some areas of higher than average population density without other areas of lower than average population density. And if population flows are endogenous, shouldn't urban economics and rural economics be part of the same general equilibrium and part of the same subject? And why call it "urban" economics if they are?
Just to be nit picky, it's not really a Prisoner's Dilemma since the equilibrium strategies are not strictly dominant. It's just an inefficient equilibrium.
Posted by: notsneaky | February 13, 2016 at 05:28 PM
And there's a huge literature in development economics on "urban bias" though it mostly attributes the "cities are too big" result to government policy.
Posted by: notsneaky | February 13, 2016 at 05:29 PM
There's a bit of a simplification on that, consider if the utility function works as follows (in R notation, mostly it reads as expected):
So for the agent controlling the x variable, the "Reaction Function" is always simply x = 0.6 regardless of y value.
Thus, in a symmetric situation, equilibrium is at x* = y* = 0.6 and it's very simple to demonstrate that neither agent can individually improve their situation from that point. Here's the graphical illustration of the same function (sorry but I felt compelled to put X on the bottom axis, because we have to have standards in this world).
Clearly both agents would be better off if they could achieve a compromise equilibrium at x = y = 0.5 which would be easy enough if they just coordinated their actions between each other with some sort of contractual instrument.
Making the jump from this abstract model to inner city living is quite something though... when you consider actually many people are perfectly happy in small houses with minimal facilities. E.g. you don't have sufficient kitchen to cook in, and you don't have space to store food, but that doesn't matter because there are a dozen good and cheap cafes within 5 minutes walk and plenty of other shops that are open long hours. That's not to say everyone wants to live like this, and that's fine because there are various other options to choose from.
Posted by: Tel | February 13, 2016 at 05:58 PM
notsneaky: I was wondering about my calling it PD. Fair point.
Tel: those are circular indifference curves, I think, so the reaction function is horizontal, so there's no strategic complementarity.
Posted by: Nick Rowe | February 13, 2016 at 08:01 PM
Yes, they are circular, and I would say "reaction function is vertical" because we all know X is on the bottom :-P
Agreed, no strategic complementarity in my example above, but that does not significantly change the point being illustrated anyhow. Consider a simple affine transform:
You can have your elliptical indifference curves if you want, but structurally I'd argue it's pretty much the same problem. At least, I don't see where this transform introduced any new and interesting behaviour into the model. Admittedly, the red line cannot be sketched in with a simple eyeball solution any more, and I'm too lazy to spend the time to calculate it out properly. However, if you kind of imagine where that red line would be, you still get the same end-result that the two parties need to coordinate with a contractual instrument if they want to optimize their situation (i.e. the Nash equilibrium leaves room for Pareto improvement).
Here's the graphic FWIW (I'm on a roll posting graphics to your site) with same colours as above via transformed coordinates:
As mentioned above, the fact that this sort of situation can in principle exist, doesn't directly lead to any conclusions about density of city living. It might give us clues about where to go looking, I'm not one of those anti-model type Austrians, I just want to see a bit more real-world data demonstrating this.
Posted by: Tel | February 13, 2016 at 09:28 PM
I would argue that the local region close to the Nash equilibrium would be a similar shape to a Prisoner's Dilemma, and the far flung regions in the corners are unlikely to be visited in any practical situation, so we can ignore those regions completely. Thus, the final analysis can borrow heavily from work already done in PD without running into difficulty.
Posted by: Tel | February 13, 2016 at 09:34 PM
Tel, no, with a PD a person would want to play x* no matter what anyone else plays. There'd be no strategic complementarity (since if the other guy raises their x you'd still want to play x*, rather than also raising it as with sc). It's a different game, although the colloquial use of "Prisoner's Dilemma" to mean "any inefficient outcome of strategic interaction" is pretty common. But since Nick's post is about clarifying the confusion between strategic complementarity and positive externalities, I thought it'd be alright for me to get nit picky and clear up that confusion too.
Posted by: notsneaky | February 13, 2016 at 10:43 PM
Or to put it in terms of the graph, with a strongly dominant strategy like in the PD, the best response function is a horizontal (or vertical, for other players) line.
Posted by: notsneaky | February 13, 2016 at 11:26 PM
notsneaky: just a semantic dispute with you, but: would we really want to insist that a game is not called "PD" unless the players have dominant strategies? Because dominant strategies are very very rare, except in very simple games where there are only 2 (or 3) strategies.
Posted by: Nick Rowe | February 14, 2016 at 07:42 AM
Well, the usual presentation of the PD involves explaining that the player has an incentive to confess regardless of what other player does. You're right though that the strong dominance in PD comes from it usually being presented as a 2x2 game, in which case to have a unique inefficient equilibrium you need these strategies to be SD (otherwise you either get 2 equilibriua, a coordination game not a PD, or the outcome is efficient)
I guess the answer depends on what you want to illustrate with the PD. One way to think of it is that it shows that you can get an inefficient outcome *even with* strongly dominant strategies.
Also if you don't insist on them SDs defining PD then you can just use the phrase "inefficient equilibrium" and it works just as well, and the only reason to say "Prisoner's Dilemma" is ... aesthetics?
Posted by: notsneaky | February 14, 2016 at 10:26 PM
Putting it another way - is "Prisoner's Dilemma" synonymous with "inefficient equilibrium" or is it a special case of the latter that we want to emphasize for some reason.
Posted by: notsneaky | February 14, 2016 at 10:28 PM
notsneaky: I'm not sure. I have tended to use "PD" perhaps as just a metaphor for any game that has a unique inefficient equilibrium, just because strict dominance seems so unlikely in more general games. But I can understand people wanting a stricter definition.
Posted by: Nick Rowe | February 14, 2016 at 11:35 PM
This might - and I'm just speculatin' - have something to do with what happens as you increase the number of players in a game. Take Cournot competition. You increase the number of firms, you approach perfect competition. If the Cournot equilibrium involved strictly dominant strategies rather than just being an inefficient equilibrium, that wouldn't happen since with strictly dominant strategies everyone would keep playing the same inefficient strategy.
One can of course think of games where increasing the number of players does not increase efficiency. But maybe it's a necessary not a sufficient condition kind of thing. If the inefficient equilibrium involves strictly dominant strategies competition won't ever help. If the inefficient equilibrium involves just best responses, then increasing the number of players might help.
I'm just making stuff up though.
Posted by: notsneaky | February 15, 2016 at 02:03 AM
Nick:
Enjoyed your post as usual. Yesterday I realized that despite my many years studying economics, I had been combining the two concepts into one by using using the apparently dreaded word "network externality."
This morning the distinction returned to being hazy and elusive.
Let me try it out with respect to payments systems. Suppose I am a member of a 10 person payment system. You join. That to me, an existing member, is a positive externality. I know longer have to rush over with a pile of bills when I need to pay you.
Now Frances is a non-member. Does your joining create a "strategic complementary for her? Before you joined, she would gain access to ten members if she joined. Now she gains access to eleven members.
Posted by: John Chant | February 15, 2016 at 03:06 PM
John: thanks!
I *think* if the choice is between joining and not-joining a payment system, we get strategic complementarity plus a positive externality for existing members when a new member joins, with no effect on non-members.
A different, more difficult case is where there are two different systems, or two different monies, like gold and silver. Menger would say there is very strong strategic complemantarity (the reaction function is not just upward-sloping, but has a slope greater than one in the neighbourhood of 50% using gold and 50% using silver). So we get two stable Nash equilibria, and an unstable equilibrium with 50% using each. In this case, if one person switches from silver to gold, that creates a positive externality for other gold-users and a negative externality for other silver-users.
Posted by: Nick Rowe | February 15, 2016 at 04:21 PM
"You can't have some areas of higher than average population density without other areas of lower than average population density."
Yes, but that doesn't really seem to grapple with the fact that, e.g., the world as a whole has become much more urbanized over time, especially in recent decades. If every Single person on earth moves into a city and robots do our farming that is an important shift, even though the average population density of the earth is the same, and the increase in density in some places is balanced by the decrease in others.
Posted by: Gene Callahan | February 17, 2016 at 11:55 AM