OK, this post is a little on the whimsical side. The argument is a lot less strong and clear than I would like it to be. But sometimes you just have to say what's in your head, and hope that will help it get clearer. Read at your own risk (as if that needed saying).
Suppose, just suppose, that the Governor of the Bank of Canada became an existentialist. And everyone knew that.
He's a free man. Each morning he wakes up to a brand new day. It doesn't matter what he did yesterday. Bygones are forever bygones. What will he set the overnight rate at today? He decides to set it at 11%. Yesterday he set it at 1%. But so what? That was yesterday.
In the face of an unexpected one thousand basis point increase in the overnight rate, the bond market rolls its eyes, yawns, and goes back to sleep. Because the bond market knows that tomorrow will be yet another brand new day for the existentialist Governor, and what he does today tells us next to nothing about what he will do tomorrow. He will be a totally different person tomorrow. One day at 11% rather than 1% is nothing in the life of a 30 year bond.
An existentialist Governor is not really a Governor. He is a daily sequence of different governors. And because his daily actions would have so little effect, he would need to make truly massive surprise changes to have any effect at all. And since he knows this, he does make massive changes. But those massive changes have zero weight on his future selves.
That, surprisingly, is exactly how monetary policy works in economic theory. At least, that's how it works in theories where it is assumed that the central bank re-optimises every period, and cannot pre-commit its future actions. The central bank is assumed to be run by an existentialist. The only reason those theories work at all is because we imagine they use quarterly data. So the central bank only has an existentialist moment four times a year.
That is not at all how monetary policy works in practice. In practice, if the Governor made a surprise thousand basis point hike in the overnight rate, the bond market would have a nervous breakdown trying to figure out why the Governor did that, and what his actions mean for the future. "Does he think that demand and inflationary pressures have suddenly gotten much stronger, so he needs that massive thousand basis point hike to offset that pressure and keep inflation on target? What does he know that we don't know? Or maybe he wants to reduce inflation to a new lower target? Or maybe, just maybe, he's trying to tell us that he wants a higher inflation target, and if we figure that out, we will be expecting higher inflation from now on, so he needs to raise the nominal interest rate to keep the real rate from falling? Or was it just a fat finger on the press release, so it doesn't mean anything, will be corrected tomorrow, and we can all go back to sleep?"
The bond market, and the stock market, and the forex market, and the supermarket, and the labour market, will all want to know what the Governor means by raising the overnight rate one thousand basis points. "What is he trying to tell us about his future actions?"
Today's action by the Governor has an almost negligible effect on anything. How his action today affects expectations of his future actions is what matters. And the Governor knows this. So he will be choosing an action that changes expectations in the way he wants them to be changed. And the market knows this. And the Governor knows this too. And so on.
We can imagine a world in which conventions get established. Suppose the market has a superstitious belief that if the overnight rate target ends in a 5, it is likely to be a temporary change; and if it ends in a 0 it is likely to be a permanent change. And the Governor knows the market has this superstition, and the market knows the Governor knows this, and so on. It's common knowledge. That superstition is enormously helpful to the Governor. If he wants to tell the market he thinks this will be a temporary change, he makes sure the new target ends in a 5. If he wants to tell the market he thinks it will be a permanent change, he makes sure the new target ends in a 0. And as long as the Governor is honest, the market will believe what he "says", even if they subsequently forget the superstition.
In an economy with that convention, the IS curve would be very spiky. Or, there would be one IS curve joining the dots which end in 5, and another IS curve joining the dots that end in 0. Two very different IS curves, with different slopes, because the effect of a change in the overnight rate depends on whether it is expected to be temporary or more permanent.
Most English-speaking people have a similar superstitious belief that the word "cat" means cat. That superstition works pretty well. It lets us all talk about cats, and understand each other. It's just a convention, of course. It doesn't matter what word we use to mean cat. Just as long as we are not all existentialists, and keep changing what words mean every new day. True existentialists can't speak English. Or even Parisian French. Why should words mean what they meant yesterday?
The word "grue" means "green until 2013, and blue thereafter". The word "bleen" means "blue until 2013, and green thereafter". In the other half of the dictionary, the word "green" means "grue until 2013, and bleen thereafter". And "blue" means "bleen until 2013, and grue thereafter".
All emeralds so far observed have been both green and grue. If we believe in inductive inference, should we expect emeralds to continue being green, or continue being grue, after 2013? Will emeralds change colour or do nothing in 2013? What do you mean by "doing nothing"? Do you mean staying green, or staying grue?
Suppose you see monetary policy change today. Do people expect monetary policy to change again or do nothing in 2013? What do you mean by "doing nothing"? Because if you think that you can project the present into the future, so that the null hypothesis is doing nothing, your actions today will depend on what you mean by "doing nothing".
Take a simple duopoly model. Two firms in an industry, each produces a good that is an imperfect substitute for the other firm's good. Write down the demand functions and cost functions for the two firms. Assume each firm maximises profits. Assume all that is common knowledge between the two firms. Assume Nash equilibrium in a one-shot game with both firms moving simultaneously.
As economists have known for centuries(?), all that is not enough to predict the outcome. There's the Cournot-Nash equilibrium, where each firm chooses a quantity to maximise profits, given the other firm's quantity. And there's the Bertrand-Nash equilibrium, where each firm chooses a price to maximise profits, given the other firm's price. And the prices and quantities chosen in Cournot-Nash are different from the prices and quantities chosen in Bertrand-Nash. Any upper year economics undergraduate could do the math to prove this. I did it once.
It matters whether the two firms speak the quantity language or speak the price language. A change in the language in which we talk about and think about the concrete reality changes that concrete reality. We get lower prices and higher output if the duopolists speak P-language than if they speak Q-language.
Sure, P-language can be translated into Q-language, and vice versa. But an unconditional statement about what price the firm will set is equivalent to a conditional statement about what quantity the firm would set, as a function of the other firms quantity, to ensure that same price. (And vice versa). And then we have re-opened the game, because there is no auctioneer to solve those two conditional reaction functions for the equilibrium.
If language matters for nuts and bolts in something as concrete as industrial organisation theory, where the practical no-nonsense feet-on-the-ground applied economists hang out, how can it not matter in monetary theory? The central bank can say things in one language which it cannot say in another language. The interest rate language they currently use does not contain negative numbers. And it is an ambiguous language when it comes to whether an increase in nominal interest rates means a tightening or a loosening of monetary policy.
The people of the concrete steppes won't like this post. Because I'm saying their concrete steps will go up or go down, depending how you talk about them. They aren't made of concrete. But it's incredibly hard, when you have gotten used to one conceptual scheme for thinking about the world, to realise that your conceptual scheme is not concrete. There is nothing essentially catty that all cats have in common. "Cat" is just a more or less useful name, a bit fuzzy round the edges, that we use to divide off some animals from others. But in economics, unlike biology, how cats behave depends on whether we call them "cats".
Von Mises said, in Human Action IIRC, that economics is reasoning about reasoning beings. That's true and important. But economics is also talking about talking beings. It might be pushing things only a little too far if I said that economics is a sub-field within philosophy of language.
[I won't be near a computer much this weekend, so won't be responding quickly to comments.]
"There's the Cournot-Nash equilibrium, where each firm chooses a quantity to maximise profits, given the other firm's quantity. And there's the Bertrand-Nash equilibrium, where each firm chooses a price to maximise profits, given the other firm's price. And the prices and quantities chosen in Cournot-Nash are different from the prices and quantities chosen in Bertrand-Nash. Any upper year economics undergraduate could do the math to prove this. I did it once.
"It matters whether the two firms speak the quantity language or speak the price language. A change in the language in which we talk about and think about the concrete reality changes that concrete reality. We get lower prices and higher output if the duopolists speak P-language than if they speak Q-language."
This sounds like an extreme form of linguistic determinism. In the real world, both firms speak the same language about prices and quantities. And neither is restricted in its choice of strategies.
Posted by: Min | November 05, 2011 at 09:25 AM
One of the things I take home form this post and from all MM thinking is that money is a different thing to rich people and poor people. To rich people money comes form asset accumulation while for poor people it comes from income streams (which come from the gracious hearts of the "job creators", bless them). Monetarists, via the central bank, are trying to influence the rich people to behave differently. These rich people are arrogant enough to think they can predict the future and when their crystal ball gets cloudy its the governments fault. The CB know that they control the largest aspect of the future, what the risk free return on money will be. As much as the job creators like to boast otherwise, they also want some sort of "social welfare" , a safe return on their money. They need to know what that safe return will be and they want it to be more than 0.25%.. So now the MMs, seeing that too many job creators are happy with their 2% bonds are trying to scare them by saying that even those will be gone and all that will be left is 0.25%. Trouble is these guys are betting they can scare the CB to raise the rates. They own all the media outlets, all the multinationals all the means of production and all the politicians. Who you gonna bet on?
Posted by: Gizzard | November 05, 2011 at 09:50 AM
Me too, I like to tell the market what's going to happen to employment and growth and where inflation is going to be next year. I wonder what would happen to the market if I just said crazy random stuff from one day to the next. Surely the market would no longer be able to read my thoughts. It would be very upsetting. Or is there some difference between me and the Fed that means the market cares more what the Fed says than what I say?
Here's the point. The Fed has instruments. They can use them now and in the future. The most they can do is say what they with do with those instruments in the future contingent on the state of of the world. That's a lot of stuff they can say. Or they can describe some less complete subset of contingencies, that may have offsetting virtues (such as having finite information content). So there's a "complete" language and any number of "sub-languages". But all of them are about contingent *concrete steps*.
Posted by: K | November 05, 2011 at 10:23 AM
Nick,
Any rules-based regime carries a large payoff to market actors if the rules are abandoned. Look at it from a speculator's viewpoint: I want to short NGDP futures because the payoff is out-sized even though the probability is lower. The bet will work if others begin to adopt the same strategy, as this raises the probability. The Fed has a tool to influence the payoff distribution too: it can raise the negative payoff significantly by promising to be "irresponsible" with future inflation.
As someone short NGDP futures, I am effectively betting that the Fed will NOT adopt such irresponsibility. The more the Fed believes MM's when they insist no change in the l.t. path of inflation is needed, the higher the chance that I will be right in this bet.
Let me put it another way: if I am short NGDP futures right now, what I fear most is that the Fed will raise the path of future inflation to a level where hedging by buying a house is almost a no-brainer. I know I will lose big if this happens. When I hear "4% inflation for two years, and then 2% inflation," I sleep peacefully at night with my short bet: no one will rush out an buy a house under that scenario.
Posted by: David Pearson | November 05, 2011 at 11:25 AM
Sounds like FDR and the gold exchange rate in the early 1930s ... FDR used "lucky numbers " he pulled out of his pajamas.
Posted by: Greg Ransom | November 05, 2011 at 12:34 PM
If you don't know what existentialism is, this article gives a really great explanation on it.
http://explainlikeakid.blogspot.com/2011/10/what-is-existentialism.html
Posted by: sarah monotl | November 05, 2011 at 06:09 PM
Gizzard: "One of the things I take home form this post and from all MM thinking is that money is a different thing to rich people and poor people. To rich people money comes form asset accumulation while for poor people it comes from income streams (which come from the gracious hearts of the "job creators", bless them). Monetarists, via the central bank, are trying to influence the rich people to behave differently."
Indeed. Ahem. We want rich people to spend money. But they won't because they will save against future taxes. But maybe we can lie to them and hope that they believe our lies. Etc., etc.
You want people to spend money? Put money into the hands of poor people. But there seems to be a taboo against that.
Posted by: Min | November 05, 2011 at 07:26 PM
I like this post. I think it's a good starting point for seeing why all the Chuck Norris posts were wrong.
The central bank rally can't pre-commit its future actions. Any commitment it has the power to make, it has the power to break. Its future actions can be pre-committed only by someone, or something, out of its own control. To the extent your choices today bind your future actions, you can't freely make those choices, because they are already bound by your choices yesterday.
In a country in which NGDP targeting has existed for a long time, it is credible. The existing history is evidence that the target is not easy to change. And the history itself can't be changed at all. But that doesn't mean that a similar target can be credibly adopted elsewhere, because the mere fact of adopting a new target, shows that the target can be easily changed.
(If it were adopted only after a few weeks of bloody street fighting or a constitutional crisis, that would be different.)
To the extent that a central bank has power through expectations, it has power only via the policies it has the least choice about. Because to the exact extent that it is able to freely choose a policy, it is unable to commit to that policy in the future.
Posted by: JW Mason | November 05, 2011 at 07:59 PM
I know. You know I know. I know you know I know. We know Henry knows, and Henry knows we know it.
We’re a knowledgeable family.
— From The Lion in Winter, Prince Geoffrey to his mother, Eleanor of Aquitaine, speaking of her husband, his father, Henry II.
Posted by: Steve Roth | November 05, 2011 at 11:18 PM
Min,
As I understand it, the problem is one of policy symmetry: putting money in the hands of the rich (expansionary monetary policy) is about as acceptable as taking it away from them (contractionary monetary policy). In terms of DIRECT changes in their stock of wealth, changes in the monetary base don't actually affect either*.
Now, consider an expansionary policy, aimed at increasing the money supply, where the poor are given cheques in the mail using underfunded state borrowing; in short, debt monetisation. That's acceptable, I assume. Yet consider a case where you want to reduce the monetary base. Do you go after the poor? It's not like with the rich, where you can change the price of assets by swapping assets for base money.
The converse of an asset swap is the same swap in reverse. The converse of handouts of freshly-printed money to the poor is taking the poor's cash by force. You could call it "taxation".
* Henry Hazlitt would rightly condemn all this reasoning, because we aren't following through the analysis e.g. the effects of monetary policy on assets, equity, and creditworthiness. And the further effects of contractionary monetary policy on interest rates & asset prices are hardly popular.
Posted by: W. Peden | November 06, 2011 at 01:16 PM
Min
The rich wont spend on anything in which they arent guaranteed a return. Virtually all spending for them is about "what can I get in return". The poor of course are just trying to have a roof, have some food, have some health care..... and all those things are already owned by the rich. Its an incredibly short sighted person who cannot see that money to the poor will always end up in some owners hands. Where as money to the rich just ends up in some politicians pocket, some think tanks propaganda machine or some trust fund for junior so he can carry on the legacy of buying control of others lives.
Posted by: Gizzard | November 06, 2011 at 02:08 PM
@ W. Peden:
The choice of who to give money to and who to take it from is largely political, no?
Aside from the question of symmetry, it makes a kind of sense to aim monetary policy at the rich. After all, who has the most money? OTOH, how does such policy affect the rest of the economy? The recession officially ended in the U. S. over two years ago, and big bankers are enjoying their bonuses again? But does that reflect the condition of the economy as a whole?
Posted by: Min | November 08, 2011 at 10:13 PM
Gizzard: "Its an incredibly short sighted person who cannot see that money to the poor will always end up in some owners hands."
As may be, but money tends to circulate, except when it doesn't. See Nick Rowe's hot potato stories.
Right now, money is not circulating well enough for unemployment to come down significantly. Even if putting money in the hands of the poor means that it hits a bottleneck when it gets to the rich, it still results in more movement than otherwise. :)
Posted by: Min | November 08, 2011 at 10:18 PM